What is Doubt and When is it Reasonable?
Paul Thagard
University of Waterloo
Thagard, P. (forthcoming). What is doubt and when is it reasonable? In M. Ezcurdia & R. Stainton & C. Viger (Eds.), New Essays in the Philosophy of Language and Mind. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, Supplementary Volume. Calgary: University of Calgary Press.
Introduction
Descartes contended that "I am obliged in the end to
admit that none of my former ideas are beyond legitimate doubt"
(Descartes 1964, p. 64). Accordingly, he adopted a method of
doubting everything: "Since my present aim was to give myself
up to the pursuit of truth alone, I thought I must do the very
opposite, and reject as if absolutely false anything as to which
I could imagine the least doubt, in order to see if I should not
be left at the end believing something that was absolutely indubitable"
(p. 31). Similarly, other philosophers have raised doubts about
the justifiability of beliefs concerning the external world, the
existence of other minds, and moral principles; philosophical
skepticism has a long history (Popkin 1979).
The concept of doubt is not only of philosophical interest, for
it plays a central role in the legal system when jurors are instructed
not to convict an accused criminal unless they are convinced of
guilt beyond a reasonable doubt. Surprisingly, however, there
is little consensus in the theory and practice of law concerning
what differentiates reasonable from unreasonable doubt. Faust
(2000a, p. 229) reports a "firestorm of controversy"
concerning the proper legal meaning of the term "reasonable
doubt," and furnishes an extensive annotated bibliography.
My aim in this paper is to propose (1) a descriptive theory of
doubt as a cognitive/emotional mental state and (2) a normative
theory of the conditions under which doubt can be viewed as reasonable.
After describing previous philosophical accounts of doubt, I develop
an account of doubt as emotional incoherence that provides a framework
for a general account of when doubt is reasonable or unreasonable
in philosophical, legal, and scientific contexts.
Cold and Hot Doubt
Social psychologists distinguish between cold cognition and
hot cognition, where the latter involves emotions tied in with
personal goals and motivations (Kunda, 1999). Similarly, I shall
distinguish between cold doubt and hot doubt, where the latter
involves an attitude toward a proposition that is emotional as
well as cognitive. Most philosophers and legal theorists have
discussed cold doubt, but I shall follow Charles Peirce in treating
doubt as hot, that is as involving an attitude toward a proposition
that has a central emotional component. First let us consider
accounts of cold doubt.
Nathan Salmon (1995) proposes the following definition for the
word "doubt":
A doubts p =def (A disbelieves p) or (A suspends judgment concerning
p)
A disbelieves p =def A believes not-p
A suspends judgment concerning p =def not-(A believes p) and not-(A
disbelieves p)
Salmon acknowledges that this definition constitutes a departure
from standard usage in that it does not require that a believer
has a grasp of a proposition and has attempted consciously to
choose between the proposition and its negation. It follows from
his definitions that for any proposition p, either A believes
p or A doubts p. This is a very odd result: it implies that
a person who has never even considered a proposition, for example,
that there are more than a million trees in Newfoundland, either
believes it or doubts it. Salmon's definition of doubt also
does not take into account the contention of Bertrand Russell
(1984, p. 142) that doubt "suggests a vacillation, an alternate
belief and disbelief." For both Salmon and Russell, doubt
is an entirely cognitive rather than emotional phenomenon, a
matter of belief and disbelief.
Similarly, Jennifer Faust's (2000b) discussion of reasonable doubt
in the law assumes that it is a purely cognitive matter. She
distinguishes two senses of doubt that generate two senses of
reasonable doubt:
S doubts1 that p =def S believes that not-P.
S doubts2 that p =def S does not believe that P.
S reasonably doubts1 that p =def S has sufficient reason to believe
that not-p.
S reasonably doubts2 that p =def S does not have sufficient reason
to believe that p.
Faust makes a convincing case that some prevalent legal instructions
concerning reasonable doubt mistakenly confuse the first and second
senses, so that jurors are told that acquitting an accused person
requires having sufficient reason to believe that the accused
was not guilty (sense 1 of "doubt" and "reasonable
doubt"). The more appropriate instruction is that acquitting
an accused person requires only not having sufficient reason to
believe that the accused was guilty (sense 2). As for Salmon
and Russell, Faust's doubt is a matter of cold cognition.
An alternative hot conception of doubt was developed by Charles
Peirce in the 1860s and 1870s. He attacked Descartes' method
of doubt by arguing that complete doubt is a mere self-deception:
"Let us not pretend to doubt in philosophy what we do not
doubt in our hearts" (Peirce 1958, p. 40). According to
Peirce, beliefs are habits of mind that guide our desires and
shape our actions. Doubt is not merely a matter or belief or
disbelief, but is an irritation that causes inquiry, which
is a struggle to attain a state of belief (p. 99). The Cartesian
exercise of questioning a proposition does not stimulate the mind
to struggle after belief, which requires a "real and living
doubt" (p. 100). According to Peirce, "the action of
thought is excited by the irritation of doubt, and ceases when
belief is attained" (p. 118). Doubt is not the result of
an internal exercise: "Genuine doubt always has an external
origin, usually from surprise" (p. 207). For Peirce, doubt
is intimately tied with goals and motivation to increase knowledge,
as well as with emotional states involving irritation, excitement
and surprise. Doubt is a matter of hot cognition.
Doubt as Emotional Incoherence
I think that Peirce's account of doubt captures much more
of the nature of real doubt than Salmon's cold account, but Peirce
does not offer a general theory of what doubt is. First it is
useful to have some concrete examples of what Peirce called "real
and living" doubt to make it clear what needs to be explained.
I am not proposing a definition of the concept of doubt, since
such analyses are rarely successful or fruitful. Rather, my aim
is to develop a theory of about the nature and causal origins
of the mental state of doubting.
Here are some real philosophical, scientific, and legal examples
of doubt:
Philosophy: Many students taking their first course in
philosophy of mind are surprised to learn that most work in the
field adopts some form of materialism, in contrast to their religious
views that assume there is a non-material soul that survives death.
The students doubt that mind is just the brain, and feel considerable
anxiety at the possible challenge to their religious beliefs.
Science: In 1983, medical researchers heard a young Australian,
Barry Marshall, propose that most peptic ulcers are caused by
infection by a newly discovered bacterium, now known as Helicobacter
pylori. The researchers strongly doubted that Marshall could
be right about the causes of ulcers, and were very annoyed that
a beginner would propose such a preposterous theory (Thagard,
1999).
Law: In 1995, the jury in the O. J. Simpson trial learned
that some of the evidence was sloppily handled and that one of
the detectives in the case had a long history of racism. For
these and other reasons they doubted that Simpson murdered his
ex-wife and quickly and enthusiastically voted to acquit him (Thagard,
forthcoming).
In each of these cases, people encountered a proposition or set
of propositions that did not fit with what they already believed,
and they reacted emotionally as well as cognitively.
These cases fit the following prototype of the mental and social
situation in which doubt arises. Note that this prototype is
not proposed as a definition of the word "doubt," but
as a description of the typical nature and origins of doubt.
Typically, people doubt a proposition when:
1. Someone makes a claim about the proposition.
2. People notice that the proposition is incoherent with their
beliefs.
3. The people care about the proposition because it is relevant
to their goals.
4. The people feel emotions related to the proposition.
5. The emotions are caused by a combination of the claim, the
incoherence, and the relevance of the proposition.
Let us examine each of these facets of doubt in more detail.
In all three of the cases I described, doubt arises by virtue
of claims made by others: mind is material, ulcers are caused
by bacteria, O. J. is guilty. But doubt does not have to arise
by virtue of a claim made by someone else. Occasional cases
of real doubt are internally engendered: I think that my gloves
are in my coat pocket, but then it occurs to me that I might have
forgotten to put them there. Hence Peirce exaggerated when he
stated that genuine doubt always has an external cause, but he
was for the most part right in understanding doubt as externally
inspired, in contrast to an internal Cartesian exercise. External
causes of doubt are most often the claims of others, as in my
prototype above, but can also be interactions with the world,
as when scientists collect data that cause them to doubt prevailing
theories. In the gloves example, my doubt that my gloves are in
my coat pocket may be caused by seeing something that reminds
me that I put my gloves elsewhere. The typical external origins
of doubt are important for the kinds of emotional states involved
in doubt, such as surprise when the world does not turn out to
be as it was expected to be, or annoyance that someone is making
a claim incoherent with one's own beliefs.
Doubt always involves the incoherence of a proposition with the
rest of what one believes. Incoherence is best understood in
terms of a theory of coherence as constraint satisfaction that
I have developed at length elsewhere (Thagard, 2000). f-On this
theory, inference is a matter of accepting and rejecting representations
on the basis of their coherence with other representations. Coherence
is determined by the constraints between representations, where
the kinds of constraint and the kinds of representation are different
in six kinds of coherence: explanatory, conceptual, perceptual,
deductive, analogical, and deliberative. For example, in explanatory
coherence, the representations are propositions and the constraints
include positive ones that arise between two propositions when
one explains another and negative ones that arise between propositions
that are contradictory or in explanatory competition. Competing
theories in science, law, and ordinary life can be evaluated by
accepting or rejecting propositions based on the extent to which
doing so maximizes satisfaction of multiple conflicting constraints.
Various algorithms for maximizing coherence are available.
A proposition is incoherent with a person's belief system when
the process of coherence maximization does not lead to its acceptance
into that belief system. The most obvious source of incoherence
is contradiction, when a claim is made that contradicts what one
already believes. But incoherence can be looser, when a claim
has weaker kinds of negative constraints than contradiction.
For example, in the ulcer case, the claim that bacteria cause
ulcers did not logically contradict the claim that excess acidity
causes ulcers, yet medical researchers saw them as competing hypotheses.
Doubt can even arise analogically, when a hypothesis is recognized
as analogous to one such as cold fusion that has previously been
recognized as dubious. So the incoherence that a doubted claim
has with a belief system need not be based on contradiction.
In all cases of doubt, a claim is not accepted because doing
so would diminish coherence.
Just as Salmon distinguishes between disbelief and suspension
of judgment, we can distinguish between strong incoherence,
in which a proposition is rejected, and weak incoherence,
in which a proposition is neither accepted nor rejected. This
can happen with the connectionist (artificial neural network)
algorithm for maximizing coherence, in which the activation of
an artificial neuron representing a proposition can vary between
1 (acceptance) and 1 (rejection), with activation close to
0 signifying a state of neither acceptance nor rejection. Doubt
requires non-acceptance, but it does not require rejection, for
it can involve either strong or weak incoherence.
Doubt does not require the conscious recognition of incoherence:
we can feel unease about a proposition without being at all aware
of the source of the discomfort. Coherence calculations, like
most inferences, are performed by the brain unconsciously, with
only some of the results being conveyed to consciousness. Hence
noticing that a proposition is incoherent with one's belief system
(step 2 in the prototype above), need not involve the conscious
thought "I can't believe that because it does not fit with
my other beliefs" but merely a negative emotional reaction
to the claim.
Step 3 in my doubt prototype posits that people only doubt propositions
that they care about, where care is a matter of relevance to their
goals, both epistemic and practical. The two main epistemic goals
are truth and understanding, where the latter is achieved by unifying
explanations. If your goals include the achievement of truth
and understanding, then you will be provoked by someone who makes
a claim that you are convinced is false. Gastroenterologists
were in part annoyed by Barry Marshall because his claims about
ulcers seemed to them false and inimical to understanding. But
personal, practical goals can also contribute to doubt: if a
claim is a potential threat to your well-being or self-esteem,
then you may be motivated to look at it more critically. For
example, the beginning philosophy students may doubt materialist
philosophy more intensely because of its potential threat to the
solace and social connections that they derive from their religious
beliefs, producing a kind of motivated inference (Kunda 1999).
Practical goals need not involve only personal interests, but
could also be concerned with the general welfare of people or
with questions of fairness. As I will discuss further below in
connection with reasonable doubt, inference in science and law
are not merely aimed at acquiring truths. Science also often
has a practical goal of increasing human welfare through useful
technology, for example using antibiotics to cure ulcers. And
the law is concerned not only to find out the truth, but also
to ensure that the accused gets a fair trial and is presumed to
be innocent until proven otherwise. Epistemic and practical
goals must be relevant to a claim, for there is no point in wasting
your time doubting (or even entertaining) a claim that you do
not care about.
There are a wide variety of emotions involved with the feeling
of doubt, most of them negative. The mildest negative emotions
associated with doubt include Peirce's irritation and the unease
and discomfort that I mentioned. These emotions can be sufficiently
vague and ill-defined that it is not even obvious what their objects
are, for example whether you are irritated by the claim that aroused
doubt or by its proponent. If a claim is not strongly incoherent
with your belief system, so that rejection is not obviously called
for, the tension between accepting and rejecting the proposition
may cause anxiety, especially if it is highly relevant to your
personal goals.
Intense negative emotions can also be associated with doubt.
If someone makes a claim that is both strongly incoherent with
your belief system and highly relevant to your epistemic and practical
goals, then doubting the claim can involve emotions such as annoyance,
outrage, and even anger. Believing that the proposed claim is
to be rejected is tied in not only with disliking the claim but
also with disliking the proponent of the claim. For example,
the medical researchers who challenged Barry Marshall called him
crazy and irresponsible, and were angry that he kept defending
claims that they thought were absurd. According to the seventeenth-century
philosopher John Wilkins (1969), doubt is a kind of fear. This
claim is not generally true, but there are cases where fear may
be part of doubt, as when a scientist fears that new data may
show a favored theory to be false.
There are also unusual cases in which doubt is associated with
positive emotions. Suppose you are told by a doctor that you
need open heart surgery, but you read on the Internet that your
condition might be treated less invasively by a new drug. Then
you doubt that you should have the surgery, and are happy at the
prospect of avoiding a risky procedure. In this case, you are
happy to doubt that you need surgery. However, if you are unsure
of which treatment to pursue, you may feel strong negative emotions
such as anxiety because you have doubts about not getting surgery
as well as about getting surgery.
We now have the ingredients of the causal network that produces
the emotions associated with doubt. Because someone makes a
claim that is incoherent with what you believe and that is relevant
to your goals, you respond emotionally to the claim and sometimes
also to the claimant. Prototypically, doubt is emotional incoherence.
Reasonable Doubt
If doubt is a cognitive/emotional state caused by the incoherence
of a claim relevant to a person's goals, then what is reasonable
doubt? This question is of philosophical, legal, and scientific
importance. In philosophy, we can ask whether the doubts raised
by Descartes, Hume and other skeptics, in ethics as well as epistemology,
are reasonable. Is it reasonable to doubt whether there is an
external world, whether the future will be like the past, and
whether there is an objective difference between right and wrong?
In the law, the issue of what constitutes reasonable doubt has
been vexing, for practical as well as theoretical reasons. For
example, the Supreme Court of Canada recently overturned a number
of convictions on the grounds that the judges in the original
trial had given an incorrect instruction to the jury concerning
the nature of reasonable doubt. Psychological experiments have
found that whether mock jurors decide to convict an accused can
be influenced by what they are told about the nature of reasonable
doubt (Koch and Devine 1999). In science, there are not only
epistemic issues about whether scientists are reasonable in doubting
a newly proposed theory, but also practical issues about when
it is reasonable to doubt the desirability of technological applications
of science. For example, were gastroenterologists in 1983 reasonable
in doubting the truth of the bacteria theory of ulcers and the
efficacy of treatment of ulcers by antibiotics? I will propose
a general account of reasonable doubt as legitimate emotional
incoherence, and then discuss its application to philosophy, law,
and science and technology.
On my view, the reasonableness of doubt is both an epistemic and
a practical matter, involving epistemic standards concerning truth
and understanding and also practical standards concerning welfare
and fairness. In keeping with the prototype of doubt that I advanced
in the last section, I will specify that doubt in a proposition
is reasonable when:
1. A claim about the proposition has been made.
2. The noticed incoherence of the proposition with other beliefs
is based on a legitimate assessment of coherence.
First, the aptness of doubt requires that a claim about a proposition
has been made, normally by someone other than the person who doubts
it. This rules out the fanciful, imaginary cases of doubt that
Peirce rightly derided. The second condition is much more demanding,
requiring that, when people come to doubt something because it
is incoherent with their beliefs, they have performed a legitimate
calculation of coherence.
Legitimacy depends on the kind of coherence involved. For explanatory
coherence, which is the kind most relevant to factual claims in
metaphysics, law, and science, the requirements of legitimacy
include:
1. The available relevant evidence has all been taken into account.
2. The available alternative hypotheses have all been taken into
account.
3. The available explanatory relations have all been used to
establish constraints among the hypotheses and evidence.
4. Constraint maximization has been performed, consciously or
unconsciously, producing a coherence judgment about what propositions
to accept or reject.
Doubt can fail to be reasonable according to these legitimacy
conditions when people make their judgments of incoherence without
taking into account all the available relevant information.
This discussion has been rather abstract, so let me now relate
it to philosophical, legal and scientific cases of reasonable
and unreasonable doubt. The philosophy students' initial doubts
about materialist theories of mind strike me as reasonable, at
least initially. They encounter the claim that there is no soul
in lectures or reading, and the claim is indeed incoherent with
their religious and metaphysical beliefs. Because they care
for both theoretical and personal reasons whether there is a soul,
they feel negative emotions such as discomfort arising from the
materialist claim. Of course, the doubt will remain reasonable
only if, as they learn more about the evidence for materialism
and against mind-body dualism, they continue to perform a legitimate
coherence calculation. My own view is that, once all the available
evidence and explanations are taken into account, materialism
has more explanatory coherence than dualism (Thagard, 2000).
But students initially do not have all this information available
to them, so their doubt is reasonable. In contrast, Cartesian
doubt about whether one exists is not reasonable: no one claims
non-existence and the hypothesis is not incoherent with other
beliefs. The same is true for Humean doubt about whether the
future will be like the past. There are no negative emotions
involved in these philosophical exercises; if there were any people
seriously worried about whether they exist, we would judge them
to be mentally ill.
In legal trials, the reasonableness of doubt depends on the kind
of legal investigation. It is of crucial importance that the
standard of "beyond reasonable doubt" that applies in
criminal trials is not used in civil trials, where jurors' conclusions
need only be based on a preponderance of evidence. A crucial
aspect of criminal trials in the English tradition is that there
is a presumption of innocence. This is clearly not related to
the epistemic goal of truth: there no reason to believe that
the priory probability of innocence is greater than that of guilt,
and in fact the conditional probability of guilt given arrest
is usually much higher than the conditional probability of innocence
given arrest. Rather, the presumption of innocence is maintained
in order to ensure that trials are fair, not just in the sense
that the accused and prosecution are treated equally, as the plaintiff
and defendant are supposed to be in civil trials, but in the stronger
sense that we place a high moral value on not convicting the innocent.
Because fairness is a goal of criminal trials in addition to
truth, negative emotions concerning claims about the guilt of
the accused can arise that are more intense than would be inspired
by explanatory coherence alone. Convicting the innocent is a
moral as well as an epistemic mistake, and appropriately provokes
outrage.
Finally, consider the reasonableness of doubt in scientific and
technological contexts. It might be assumed that scientific doubt
is a purely epistemic matter, but Richard Rudner (1961, pp. 32-33)
has convincingly argued otherwise:
Since no scientific hypothesis is ever completely verified, in
accepting a hypothesis on the basis of evidence, the scientist
must make the decision that the evidence is sufficiently strong
or that the probability is sufficiently high to warrant the acceptance
of the hypothesis. Obviously, our decision with regard to the
evidence and how strong is "strong enough" is going
to be a function of the importance, in the typically ethical sense,
of making a mistake in accepting or rejecting the hypothesis.
Thus, to take a crude but easily manageable example, if the hypothesis
under consideration stated that a toxic ingredient of a drug
was not present in lethal quantity, then we would require a relatively
high degree of confirmation or confidence before accepting the
hypothesis-for the consequences of making a mistake here are exceedingly
grave by our moral standards. In contrast, if our hypothesis
stated that, on the basis of some sample, a certain lot of machine-stamped
belt buckles was not defective, the degree of confidence we would
require would be relatively lower. How sure we must be before
we accept a hypothesis depends on how serious a mistake would
be.
Thus doubt in science is in part a function of our practical goal
of avoiding harm that might result from premature acceptance of
a hypothesis. In theoretical astrophysics, the risk of harm
is trivial, so doubt can be based largely on epistemic goals,
but doubts can have a partially practical basis in areas like
medicine (relevant to treating the sick) and nuclear physics (relevant
to the construction of power plants and bombs). Just as the concern
to acquit the innocent can intensify doubts in legal contexts,
so the concern to avoid technological harm can intensify doubts
in scientific contexts.
Medical doubts can be reasonable for both epistemic and practical
reasons. When gastroenterologists first encountered the bacterial
theory of ulcers, they had strong negative emotional reactions
in part because it was incoherent with their beliefs about the
causes of ulcers and the absence of bacteria in the stomach, but
also because of their concern about people being treated inappropriately.
Their doubts about Barry Marshall's views were reasonable in 1983,
because there was little evidence then that bacteria cause ulcers
and none that killing the bacteria could cure ulcers. By 1994,
however, the situation had changed dramatically as the result
of carefully designed studies that showed that many people's ulcers
had been cured by the right combination of antibiotics. At this
point, coherence with the relevant medical information required
acceptance of the bacterial theory of ulcers, so doubt was unreasonable.
Many epistemologists think that rational belief fixation is a
probabilistic rather than a coherence-based process, so that reasonable
doubt depends on the probability of a claim. For example, Davidson
and Pargetter (1987) give three requirements for a guilty verdict:
(a) the probability of guilt given the evidence is very high,
(b) the evidence on which the probability is based is very reliable,
and
(c) the probability of guilt is highly resilient relative to
any possible evidence.
But there are powerful reasons why probability theory is not the
appropriate tool for understanding reasonable doubt.
First, the interpretation of probability is problematic in legal,
scientific, and philosophical contexts. It is obvious that the
probability of guilt given the evidence is not the objective,
statistical sense of probability as a frequency in a population:
we have no data that allow us to say in a particular trial that
the accused would be guilty in a specifiable proportion of such
trials. So probability must be some kind of logical relation
that has never been clearly defined, or a subjective degree of
belief.
Second, there is considerable psychological evidence that people's
degrees of belief do not obey the rules of the probability calculus
(Kahneman, Slovic, and Tversky 1982; Tversky and Koehler 1994).
Many psychological experiments have shown that the degrees of
confidence that people place in propositions are often not in
keeping with the rules of probability theory. Probability theory
is a relatively recent invention, having been developed only in
the seventeenth century (Hacking 1975). Yet people have been
making judgments of uncertainty for thousands of years, without
the aid of probability theory. Coherence provides a much more
plausible descriptive and normative account of non-statistical
human inference than does probability theory.
Third, probability theory is often orthogonal to the aims and
practice of law. Cohen and Bersten (1990) argue that high probability
is not even a necessary condition of finding someone guilty, which
requires satisfying a number of legal rules that must be followed
in order to ensure that the accused is given the benefit of the
presumption of innocence. Allen (1991, 1994) has described numerous
ways in which deliberation in legal trials much better fits a
coherence account than a probabilistic one.
Fourth, there are technical reasons why probabilities are difficult
to compute in real-life cases in law and other areas. A full
probability calculation is impossible in cases involving more
than the handful of propositions, because the size of a full joint
distribution increases exponentially with the number of propositions.
Powerful computational tools have been developed for calculation
of probabilities in Bayesian networks, but they require more conditional
probabilities than are usually available and strong assumptions
of independence that are rarely satisfiable. Computing probabilities
in legal and similar cases is much more difficult than coherence
computations based on maximization of constraint satisfaction.
Hence incoherence is a more plausible basis for reasonable
doubt than low probability.
Finally, probability does not provide the basis for understanding
reasonable doubt because it is not directly tied in with emotion.
I have argued that doubt is a mental state that usually involves
negative emotions such as discomfort and fear, whereas probability
judgments are purely cognitive. In contrast, coherence judgments
routinely give rise to positive emotions such as feelings of satisfaction
and even beauty, whereas incoherence judgments give rise to negative
emotions such as anxiety (self-reference omitted). If doubt is
emotional incoherence, then there must be more to reasonable doubt
than just a probability calculation.
Conclusion
This paper has advanced and defended several novel claims
about the nature of doubt and reasonable doubt. First, doubt
is not just a cold cognitive matter of belief and disbelief, but
also involves a hot, emotional reaction to a claim that has been
made. Second, doubt is not based on the low probability of a
claim, but on its incoherence with a thinker's beliefs and goals,
where coherence can be computed in a psychologically realistic
manner by parallel satisfaction of multiple constraints. Third,
what makes a doubt reasonable is not a probability calculation,
but a coherence computation that takes into account constraints
based on the full available range of evidence, hypotheses, and
explanatory and other relations. Reasonable doubt is legitimate
emotional incoherence.
Acknowledgments: I am grateful to Christine Freeman
for research assistance, and to her, Jing Zhu, Marcia Sokolowski,
and Tim Kenyon for helpful suggestions.
References
Allen, R. J. (1991). "The nature of juridical proof."
Cardozo Law Review 373: 373-422.
Allen, R. J. (1994). "Factual ambiguity and a theory of evidence."
Northwestern University Law Review 88: 604-660.
Cohen, S. and S. Bersten (1990). "Probability out of court:
Notes on 'Guilt beyond reasonable doubt'." Australasian
journal of philosophy 68: 229-240.
Davidson, B. and B. Pargetter (1987). "Guilt beyond reasonable
doubt." Australasian journal of philosophy 65: 182-187.
Faust, J. (2000). "Proof beyond a reasonable doubt: An annotated
bibliographny." The APA Newsletters (American Philosophical
Association) 99(2 (spring)): 229-235.
Faust, J. (2000). "Reasonable doubt jury instructions."
The APA Newsletters (American Philosophical Association) 99(2,
spring): 226-229.
Hacking, I. (1975). The emergence of probability. Cambridge, Cambridge
University Press.
Kahneman, D., P. Slovic, et al. (1982). Judgment under uncertainty:
Heuristics and biases. New York, Cambridge University Press.
Koch, C. M. and D. J. Devine (1999). "Effects of reasonable
dobut definition and inclusion of a lesser charge on jury verdicts."
Law and Human Behavior 23: 653-674.
Kunda, Z. (1999). Social cognition. Cambridge, MA, MIT Press.
Peirce, C. S. (1958). Charles S. Peirce: Selected writings. New
York, Dover.
Popkin, R. H. (1979). The history of scepticism from Erasmus to
Spinoza. Berkeley, University of California Press.
Russell, B. (1984). Theory of knowledge (Collected papers, vol.
7). London, George Allen & Unwin.
Salmon, N. (1995). "Being of two minds: Belief with doubt."
Nous 29: 1-20.
Thagard, P. (1999). How scientists explain disease. Princeton,
Princeton University Press.
Thagard, P. (2000). Coherence in thought and action. Cambridge,
MA, MIT Press.
Thagard, P. (forthcoming). "Why wasn't O. J. convicted:
Emotional coherence in legal inference," Cognition and Emotion.
Tversky, A. and D. J. Koehler (1994). "Support theory: A
nonextensional representation of subjective probability."
Psychological Review 101: 547-567.
Wilkins, J. (1969). Of the principles and duties of natural religion.
New York: Johnson Reprint Corp.
Back to emotion articles table of contents.
Back to Computational Epistemology Laboratory.